Skip to content
Snippets Groups Projects
ontology_2015.xml 78.99 KiB
<?xml version="1.0" encoding="UTF-8"?>
<?xml-model href="http://www.zfdg.de/sites/default/files/schema/tei_zfdg.rnc" type="application/relax-ng-compact-syntax"?>

<TEI xmlns:xsi="http://www.w3.org/2001/XMLSchema-instance" xmlns="http://www.tei-c.org/ns/1.0">
    <teiHeader>
        <fileDesc>
            <titleStmt>
                <title>
                    <biblStruct>
                        <analytic>
                            <title level="a">What People Said: The Theoretical Foundations of a
                                Minimal Doxographical Ontology and Its Use in the History of
                                Philosophy</title>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp>
                                    <persName>
                                        <name role="marc_aut">
                                            <forename>Stefan</forename>
                                            <surname>Heßbrüggen-Walter</surname>
                                        </name>
                                        <email>early.modern.thought.online@gmail.com</email>
                                        <idno type="gnd">141879335</idno>
                                        <idno type="orcid">0000-0002-9383-026X</idno>
                                    </persName>
                                </resp>
                                <orgName>National Research University Higher School of Economics,
                                    Moskau</orgName>
                            </respStmt>
                            <!-- <idno type="doi">xxx</idno> -->
                            <idno type="doi">10.17175/sb001_001</idno>
                            <idno type="zfdg">sb001.001</idno>
                            <idno type="url">http://www.zfdg.de/node/118</idno>
                            <idno type="ppn">826998763</idno>
                            <date when="2015-02-19">19.02.2015</date>
                        </analytic>
                        <monogr>
                            <title level="j">Zeitschrift für digitale Geisteswissenschaften</title>
                            <title level="m">Sonderband: Grenzen und Möglichkeiten der Digital
                                Humanities</title>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp><name role="marc_edt"
                                            ><forename>Constanze</forename><surname>Baum</surname><email>baum@hab.de</email></name><idno
                                        type="gnd">132852896</idno></resp>
                                <orgName>Herzog August Bibliothek</orgName>
                            </respStmt>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp><name role="marc_edt"
                                            ><forename>Thomas</forename><surname>Stäcker</surname><email>staecker@hab.de</email></name><idno
                                        type="gnd">141905573</idno></resp>
                                <orgName>Herzog August Bibliothek</orgName>
                            </respStmt>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp>Publiziert von</resp>
                                <orgName role="marc_pbl">Herzog August Bibliothek</orgName>
                            </respStmt>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp>Transformation der Word Vorlage nach TEI</resp>
                                <persName/>
                                <name role="marc_trc">
                                    <surname>Steyer</surname>
                                    <forename>Timo</forename>
                                    <idno type="gnd">1053806175</idno>
                                </name>
                            </respStmt>
                            <respStmt>
                                <resp>Übersetzung des Abstract ins Englische</resp>
                                <name role="marc_trl"
                                        ><forename>Kathleen</forename><surname>Smith</surname></name>
                            </respStmt>
                            <availability status="free">
                                <p>Available at <ref target="http://www.zfdg.de"
                                        >http://www.zfdg.de</ref></p>
                            </availability>
                            <biblScope unit="sonderband">1</biblScope>
                            <biblScope unit="artikel">12</biblScope>
                        </monogr>
                    </biblStruct>
                </title>
            </titleStmt>
            <editionStmt>
                <edition>Elektronische Ausgabe nach TEI P5</edition>
            </editionStmt>
            <publicationStmt>
                <!-- Publikationsangaben zum Sonderband-->
                <distributor>
                    <name><orgName>Herzog August Bibliothek Wolfenbüttel</orgName></name>
                </distributor>
                <idno type="doi">10.17175/sb001</idno>
                <idno type="ppn">826997821</idno>
                <idno type="url">http://www.zfdg.de/sonderbaende/001</idno>
                <date when="2015-02-19">19.02.2015</date>
                <authority><name>Herzog August
                    Bibliothek</name><address><addrLine/></address></authority>
                <authority><name>Forschungsverbund
                    MWW</name><address><addrLine/></address></authority>
                <availability status="free">
                    <p> Sofern nicht anders angegeben </p>
                    <licence target="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/">CC BY SA
                        4.0</licence>
                </availability>
                <availability status="free">
                    <p> Available at <ref target="workID">http://www.zfdg.de"&gt; (c)
                            Forschungsverbund MWW</ref>
                    </p>
                </availability>
            </publicationStmt>
            <sourceDesc>
                <p>Ausgewählte Beiträge der DHd-Tagung 2014 in Passau</p>
            </sourceDesc>
        </fileDesc>
        <encodingDesc>
            <!-- Angaben  zur Enstehung des Textes -->
            <editorialDecl>
                <p>Transformation der WORD-Vorlage nach XML/TEI-P5 durch Apache TIKA 1.7 und
                    XSLT</p>
            </editorialDecl>
            <editorialDecl>
                <p xml:lang="de">Lektorat des Textes durch die Redaktion.</p>
            </editorialDecl>
            <editorialDecl>
                <p>Medienrechte liegen bei den Autoren</p>
            </editorialDecl>
            <editorialDecl>
                <p>All links checked<date when="2016">24.05.2016</date></p>
            </editorialDecl>
        </encodingDesc>
        <profileDesc>
            <creation>Einreichung für den Sonderband 1 der Zeitschrift für digitale
                Geisteswissenschaften</creation>
            <langUsage>
                <language ident="en">Text in English</language>
                <language ident="en">Abstract in Deutsch</language>
            </langUsage>
            <!-- Verschlagwortung -->
            <!-- tadriah durch die Redaktion -->

            <!-- gnd -->
            <textClass>
                <keywords scheme="gnd">
                    <term>Wissensrepräsentation<ref target="4049534-6"/></term>
                    <term>Philosophie <ref target="4045791-6"/></term>
                    <term>Ontologie <ref target="4827894-4"/></term>
                </keywords>
            </textClass>
        </profileDesc>
        <!-- Angaben zur vorliegenden Version -->
        <revisionDesc>
            <change><!-- Each change should include @who and @when as well as a brief note on what was done. --></change>
        </revisionDesc>
    </teiHeader>
    <text>
        <body>
            <div>
                <div type="abstract">
                    <argument xml:lang="de">
                        <p>Üblicherweise beruht das Design von Ontologien auf der Annahme, dass die
                            Bedeutung einer Proposition sich aus der Bedeutung ihrer Elemente
                            (Begriffe) und ihrer syntaktischen Struktur ergibt. Die Reichweite
                            dieses ›Prinzips der Kompositionalität‹ ist jedoch innerhalb der
                            Semantik strittig. Die Gegner des Prinzips verteidigen den Primat der
                            Satzbedeutung und leiten die Bedeutung von Begriffen aus ihrem Beitrag
                            zur Satzbedeutung ab. Angesichts dieses Sachstandes argumentiert der
                            Aufsatz zugunsten eines Zugangs zum Design von Ontologien, der keine
                            Stellungnahme in dieser Debatte voraussetzt. Die hier vorgeschlagene
                            ›minimale doxographische Ontologie‹ dient als heuristisches Werkzeug zur
                            Erfassung unbekannter oder komplexer Gegenstandsbereiche. In ihr werden
                            Satzbedeutungen als unanalysierbar angesehen und auf einen Träger des
                            propositionalen Inhalts (Personen oder Texte) bezogen. Die Stärken eines
                            solchen Ansatzes werden zunächst anhand eines vereinfachten Beispiels
                            erörtert, einer Analyse von juristischen Begriffsdefinitionen
                            alkoholischer Getränke. Ein komplexerer Anwendungsfall betrifft die
                            doxographische Analyse von Debatten in der Geschichte der
                            frühneuzeitlichen Philosophie. Schließlich erörtert der Aufsatz kurz,
                            wie ein solcher Ansatz erweitert werden kann, indem Ontologien als
                            hermeneutische Werkzeuge zur Deutung von Quellen der
                            Philosophiegeschichte verwendet werden. </p>
                    </argument>
                    <argument xml:lang="en">
                        <p>Traditionally, ontology engineering is based on the presumption that the
                            meaning of a proposition results from the combination of the meaning of
                            its elements (concepts) and its syntactical structure. The reach of this
                            ›principle of compositionality‹ is, however, a contested topic in
                            semantics. Its opponents defend the primacy of propositional meaning and
                            derive the meaning of concepts from their contribution to propositional
                            meaning. In this situation, this paper argues for an approach to
                            ontology design that does not presuppose a stance in this debate. The
                            proposed ›minimal doxographical ontology‹ is intended as a heuristic
                            tool charting unknown or complex domains. It regards propositional
                            meaning as atomic and relates it to a bearer of propositional content
                            (persons or texts). The strengths of such an approach are first
                            discussed in a simplified example, the analysis of legal stipulations on
                            alcoholic beverages. A more complex use case concerns the doxographical
                            analysis of debates in the history of early modern philosophy. In
                            closing, the paper sketches briefly how this approach may be extended
                            using ontologies as hermeneutic tools in the interpretation of sources
                            from the history of philosophy.</p>
                    </argument>
                </div>
                <div type="chapter">
                    <head>1. Introduction</head>
                    <p>In recent years, technologies of knowledge representation that are usually
                        subsumed under the heading of the ›semantic web‹ have been used within the
                        digital humanities in disciplines as diverse as literary studies (e. g.
                        regarding <ref
                            target="http://www.digitalhumanities.org/dhq/vol/3/4/000068/000068.html"
                            >the ontology of fictional characters</ref>), philosophy (<ref
                            target="http://www.webcitation.org/query?url=http://wab.uib.no/wab_philospace.page&amp;date=2014-09-26"
                            >the Wittgenstein ontology</ref>), or history (<ref
                            target="http://www.webcitation.org/query?url=http://linkedevents.org/ontology/2010-10-07/&amp;date=2014-09-26"
                            >LODE</ref>, an ontology for the description of historical events).
                        Thinking about the ›semantic web‹ comes most naturally to digital humanists
                        approaching the discipline from what could be called a ›cultural heritage‹
                        angle, e. g. librarians, archivists, or curators. In these areas, the
                        production of meaningful metadata is part of everyday workflows; the
                        transition from cataloguing guidelines to machine-readable metadata
                        standards to semantic web languages like RDF comes quite naturally and is an
                        important step in fighting the ›siloisation‹ of digital collections by
                        embedding them in a web of ›linked open data‹.<note type="footnote"> Cf.
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#kemmann_grasping_2014">Kemmann
                                2014</ref>, section <quote>Embracing Technology</quote>.</note></p>
                    <p>Whether ontologies are an important part of the tool set of the digital
                        humanist is still a disputed question.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#kohle_bildwissenschaft_2013">Kohle
                                2013</ref>, p. 26f. with further references.</note> Some of the more
                        radical defenders of ontologies are unperturbed by this criticism. They
                        contend that ontologies are capable of not just representing or modelling
                        knowledge, but that they capture features of mind-independent reality.<note
                            type="footnote"> Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#smith_ontology_2014">Smith 2004</ref>, passim.</note> This
                        may even be true for artefacts.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#jansen_artefakte_2013">Jansen
                                2013</ref>, passim.</note></p>
                    <p>Whether semantic web technologies are a good fit for a given use case is,
                        however, first of all a technological problem that probably should not be
                        solved on purely philosophical grounds. Nevertheless, philosophy may be able
                        to contribute to some foundational debates in the digital humanities, if its
                        function is not taken to consist in the provision of foundations, but of
                        ›maieutic impulses‹ that help to explicate hidden presuppositions and
                        stimulate to rethink unacknowledged biases and blind spots.</p>
                    <p>In this spirit, this paper discusses one such unacknowledged presupposition
                        of ontology design. Both the knowledge to be modelled in an ontology and the
                        ontology itself are necessarily articulated in propositional form.
                        Correspondingly, the formal structure of ontology languages (like the Web
                        Ontology Language OWL) are consciously modelled on central premises of
                        formal semantics, first and foremost the ›principle of compositionality‹.
                        This ancestry, however, may not be as innocuous as it seems, because
                        philosophers of language discuss controversially whether the impact of the
                        principle of compositionality is limited by a second principle, the ›context
                        principle‹. Thus, those interested in the capabilities of ontologies for
                        modelling knowledge must first clarify the possible impact of these debates
                        on ontology design.</p>
                    <p>The most appropriate strategy in such uncharted territory is ›risk
                        avoidance‹. Accordingly, it may be possible to use the tools of the semantic
                        web in an unassuming and modest manner, as a heuristic tool for mapping
                        vague, complicated, or partially unknown domains. I will first discuss the
                            <hi rend="italic">raison d'être</hi> for such a modest approach using a
                        somewhat contrived example and show some problems we encounter in trying to
                        extend the well-known wine ontology. It has already been shown how the
                        modelling of certain domains can profit from analytical restraint, namely if
                        we desist from analysing propositional content into component terms and bind
                        this content to the existence of concrete spatiotemporal entities as their
                        ›bearers‹. The fruitfulness of such a minimal ontology of discourses
                        depends, however, on use cases in ›real life‹. Hence, the proposed ›ontology
                        of what people said‹ is applied to a ›doxographical map‹ of a spatially and
                        temporally circumscribed discourse in the history of philosophy, the debate
                        about the proper definition of the term ›philosophy‹ in early modern Iberian
                        philosophy.</p>
                    <p>The history of philosophy is, of course, more than just doxography. It should
                        ideally be complemented by interpretations of what people said. In my
                        conclusion, I will sketch how we may use the resources of semantic web
                        technologies to describe the conceptual hierarchies that are implicated by
                        what philosophers (and, possibly, others) have to say. However, it is
                        important to keep in mind that in the light of the foundational discussions
                        of the first part of this paper, such ontologies will always be
                        interpretations, leaving room for controversy and dissent that is probably
                        inevitable if we try to capture the meaning of a text. This is true
                        regardless of the medium we use to express our findings.</p>
                </div>
                <div type="chapter">
                    <head>2. Ontologies, Compositionality, Contextuality</head>
                    <p>In a first approximation, ontologies can be defined as <quote>explicit formal
                            specifications of the terms in the domain and relations among
                            them</quote>.<note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#noy_ontology_2001">Noy / McGuiness
                                2001</ref>, p. 1.</note> Such a specification determines <quote>a
                            common vocabulary for researchers who need to share information in a
                            domain. It includes machine-interpretable definitions of basic concepts
                            in the domain and relations among them</quote>.<note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#noy_ontology_2001">Noy / McGuiness
                                2001</ref>, p. 1.</note> Moreover, such a specification is supposed
                        to be indispensable for ›analyzing domain knowledge‹.<note type="footnote">
                            Cf. <ref type="bibliography" target="#noy_ontology_2001">Noy / McGuiness
                                2001</ref>, p. 2.</note> OWL knows two sorts of concepts: classes
                        that <quote>provide an abstraction mechanism for grouping resources with
                            similar characteristics</quote><note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#dean_ontology_2004">Dean / Schreiber
                                2004</ref>, section 3.</note> and that are defined in so-called
                        ›class axioms‹, and properties which are defined in so-called ›properties
                            axioms‹.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#dean_ontology_2004">Dean / Schreiber 2004</ref>, section
                            3.2.3.</note> The third category of statements to be found in an OWL
                        document concerns facts about individuals.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#dean_ontology_2004">Dean / Schreiber
                                2004</ref>, section 4.</note> All statements are composed out of
                        classes, properties, and constants as building blocks. These building blocks
                        must have been defined beforehand: their intension must be known, before
                        statements can be constructed.</p>
                    <p>This means that ontology engineering is firmly rooted in a theory of meaning
                        based on Frege's ›principle of compositionality‹: the <quote>[…] meaning of
                            a complex expression is determined by its structure and the meanings of
                            its constituents</quote>.<note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#szabo_compositionality_2013">Szabó
                                2013</ref>, section 1.</note> This nexus raises interesting
                        questions. Those who believe that ontologies may be capable of modelling
                        knowledge in a given domain without being committed to the stronger view
                        that they capture features of mind-independent reality may be content to
                        limit the scope of compositionality to a given language.<note
                            type="footnote"> In this case, the definition of compositionality is
                            formulated relative to a given language. Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#szabo_compositionality_2013">Szabó 2013</ref>, section 1.1:
                                <quote>For every complex expression e in L, the meaning of e in L is
                                determined by the structure of e in L and the meanings of the
                                constituents of e in L.</quote></note> Or they could maintain that
                        it only applies to the formal language which is used for articulating the
                        model of a domain, because artificial languages can be construed in such a
                        way as to exhibit compositionality as a feature. Those who subscribe to a
                        more realist interpretation of concepts in an ontology might probably have
                        to accept the stronger thesis of ›cross-linguistic compositionality‹:
                            <quote>For every complex expression e in L, the meaning of e in L is
                            functionally determined through a single function for all possible human
                            languages by the structure of e in L and the meanings of the
                            constituents of e in L</quote>.<note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#szabo_compositionality_2013">Szabó
                                2013</ref>, section 1.4.</note></p>
                    <p>But even if people may have reasoned disagreements about the scope of
                        compositionality, the ›compositionalist‹ bias is apparently built into the
                        very notion of an ontology as a ›common vocabulary for researchers‹.
                        However, this first Fregean principle conflicts with a second also discussed
                        in relation to his philosophy of language, the ›principle of contextuality‹
                        (or ›context principle‹): <quote>The meaning of an expression is determined
                            by the meanings of all complex expressions in which it occurs as a
                            constituent.</quote><note type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#szabo_compositionality_2013">Szabó
                                2013</ref>, section 1.6.4.</note> So whereas compositionalists hold
                        that the meaning of a proposition is the sum total of its parts with the
                        semantic contribution of the structure of the proposition, contextualists
                        presume that propositional meaning comes first and that the meaning of the
                        constituents of a proposition depends on their role in all other
                        propositions in which they are contained.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#szabo_compositionality_2013">Szabó
                                2013</ref>, section 1.6.4: <quote>Compositionality is about
                                bottom-up meaning-determination, while the context principle about
                                top-down meaning-determination.</quote></note> But, again, the scope
                        of this priority claim must be determined precisely. In the context of this
                        paper, it is helpful to follow Stainton and to distinguish three different
                        understandings of the priority expressed in context principles, namely
                        methodological, metasemantical, and ›psychological‹ interpretations of this
                        priority of propositional over conceptual meaning.<note type="footnote"> Cf.
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#stainton_context_2006">Stainton
                                2006</ref>, p. 109f. Helpful discussions of the role of both
                            principles in Frege can be found in <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#janssen_frege_2001">Janssen 2001</ref>, passim. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#lemanski_urspruenge_2013">Lemanski
                                2013</ref>, passim, shows convincingly that the context principle is
                            an essential element of (neo-)Aristotelian logic.</note></p>
                    <p>In a <hi rend="italic">methodological</hi> perspective, we assume that an
                        analysis of the meaning of subsentential expressions must take into account
                        the context of the proposition they appear in. This understanding of
                        propositional priority may even be compatible with compositionality, because
                        we can understand how the meaning of a subsentential expression appearing in
                        a proposition that we understand can be isolated and transferred into new
                        contexts, allowing us to express a proposition that we had not yet
                        understood. In other words, we may need both compositionality and
                        contextuality of meaning in order to explain linguistic creativity, the
                        capability of expressing new thoughts by recombining elements which we
                        already understand.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#stainton_context_2006">Stainton 2006</ref>, p.
                        111.</note></p>
                    <p>But this does not mean that we are necessarily committed to the stronger <hi
                            rend="italic">metasemantic</hi> thesis that propositional meaning is in
                        some substantial sense the only (or only the most relevant) source for the
                        meaning of subsentential expressions. If this stronger thesis were
                        applicable to the methodology of ontology design, the project as such might
                        well be hopeless, because the recombination of terms could always lead to
                        mutations in meaning that are unforeseeable for the designer.</p>
                    <p>The <hi rend="italic">psychological </hi>thesis states that competent
                        speakers of a natural language cannot grasp the meaning of subsentential
                        expressions in isolation. Proponents of this view are probably sceptical
                        with regard to the attempt to represent online resources by applying
                        subsentential expressions to them: for them, tagging as such cannot be a
                        meaningful linguistic activity. Even though such radical criticism may be
                        misplaced, we should keep in mind that the vision of the semantic web is
                        built around the notion of knowledge. And – difficult philosophical problems
                        with non-propositional forms of knowledge like knowing-how or foundational
                        perceptual beliefs notwithstanding – an ontology can only codify knowledge
                        that can be explicated in propositional form. So even if we do not subscribe
                        to the strong psychological thesis that subsentential expressions as such
                        are basically meaningless, we could still accept the methodological
                        guideline that ontology design is concerned with knowledge that <hi
                            rend="italic">can </hi>be expressed or explicated in propositional form.
                        Implicit awareness of the meaning of subsentential expressions thus should
                        always be explicated in propositional form, regardless of whether competent
                        speakers can use or understand such expressions in isolation.<note
                            type="footnote">
                            <ref type="bibliography" target="#shirky_ontology_">Shirky</ref> has not
                            helped the debate along by presenting ontologies and tagging as
                            alternative, but equivalent modes of representing online resources. On
                            the most fundamental level, both technologies solve different problems.
                            Tags are not statements; therefore, they do not encode knowledge. It may
                            be granted that tags are an efficient means for crowd sourced
                            classification and categorisation. But these are not the only – and
                            probably not the most important – use cases for ontologies. Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#shirky_ontology_">Shirky</ref>,
                            passim.</note></p>
                    <p>So even those ontology designers who would subscribe to compositionality as
                        an essential constituent of their self-understanding still face interesting
                        problems: should we presume that ontologies mirror cross-linguistic
                        universals or is their usefulness limited to speakers within a given
                        linguistic community? Do ontologies mostly track extensions, i. e. the
                        reference of terms, or should we give them an intensional interpretation as
                        well, taking into account their meaning? Do we accept the notion that
                        statements in an ontology are fully devoid of context, so that their meaning
                        really consists of nothing but the sum total of subsentential meanings and
                        the contribution made by syntax?</p>
                    <p>In thinking about these questions we should never lose track of the fact that
                        ontologies are no end in themselves: they are technological instruments, so
                        that their scope and utility is determined first and foremost by pragmatic
                        considerations. It is therefore imprudent to assume that in order to build
                        an ontology it is necessary to choose one side in these complex and
                        unresolved philosophical debates. We should rather ask ourselves to what
                        extent our understanding of ontology design is determined by unacknowledged
                        biases in our implicit theories of meaning and whether it is possible to
                        build ontologies in a way that is not committed to any explicit stance.</p>
                    <p>Such a minimal understanding, at least on the heuristic level, of coming to
                        terms with a given domain would consist in two decisive moves:</p>
                    <list type="ordered">
                        <item>The meaning of propositions (i. e. their ›propositional content‹) is
                            taken to be opaque, it is only referred to by a name. This allows us to
                            avoid any commitment whether or not in a particular case the meaning of
                            a proposition can in fact be analysed compositionally.</item>
                        <item>Propositional contents are only allowed, if they can be connected to a
                            spatio-temporal entity (mostly a person or a document) that articulates
                            a propositional attitude towards this content, i. e. asserts, denies, or
                            reflects upon the content in question. In other words, the propositional
                            content designated by the name ›wine is made of grapes‹ is not to be
                            analysed into a subject term designating a drink, an object term
                            designating fruit, and a relation term designating the process of
                            turning fruit into a drink. And it is not to be admitted, unless we can
                            trace this content to a person or document that either asserts, denies,
                            or reflects on the propositional content ›wine is made from
                                grapes‹.<note type="footnote"> So what we model are intentional
                                objects and attitudes towards these objects rather than the objects
                                themselves.</note></item>
                    </list>
                    <p>It should be noted that the opacity of propositional meanings is not taken to
                        be absolute. We still can and should talk about subject terms, object terms,
                        and relation terms contributing to the constitution of propositional
                        content. But we can do so without preconceived notions about <hi
                            rend="italic">how</hi> single terms contribute to the meaning of the
                        propositions they appear in. In order to elucidate this point, I will
                        compare the approach proposed here to standard procedures of modelling
                        knowledge about statements, i. e. reification. But first it will be helpful
                        to discuss a simplified example that is meant to demonstrate that using the
                        approach proposed here we can deal in a simple and transparent manner with
                        inconsistent statements within a domain as well as with statements that may
                        prove to be troublesome when related to other domains.<note type="footnote">
                            This second requirement is particularly relevant, because a central
                            promise of ontologies is interoperability, which is why it employs
                            generic technologies like <quote>URIs (a generic means to identify
                                entities or concepts in the world), HTTP (a simple yet universal
                                mechanism for retrieving resources, or descriptions of resources),
                                and RDF (a generic graph-based data model with which to structure
                                and link data that describes things in the world)</quote>. Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#heath_linked_">Heath</ref>, section
                                <quote>What is Linked Data?</quote>.</note></p>
                </div>
                <div type="chapter">
                    <head>3. Legal Wine</head>
                    <p>§175-2-2 of the Legislative Rule 175CSR 2 governing the activities of the
                        West Virginia Alcohol Beverage Control Commission stipulates that wine in
                        the sense of West Virginia state law is </p>
                    <p><quote>any beverage obtained by the fermentation of the natural content of
                            fruits, or other agricultural products, containing sugar and includes,
                            but is not limited to, still wines, champagne and other sparkling wines,
                            carbonated wines, imitation wines, vermouth, cider, perry, sake, or
                            other similar beverages offered for sale or sold as wines containing not
                            less than seven percent (7%) nor more than twenty-four percent (24%)
                            alcohol by volume.</quote><note type="footnote"> West Virginia Alcohol
                            Beverage Control Administration, Definition 2.21.</note>
                    </p>
                    <p>Beer is defined as <quote>any beverage obtained by the fermentation of
                            barley, malt, hops, or any other similar product or substitute, and
                            containing more alcohol than that of nonintoxicating beer or
                            nonintoxicating craft beer</quote>.<note type="footnote"> West Virginia
                            Alcohol Beverage Control Administration, Definition 2.3.</note>
                        Alcoholic liquors are defined as <quote>alcohol, beer, including barley
                            beer, wine, <hi rend="italic">including barley wine </hi>[my emphasis]
                            and distilled spirits, […]</quote>.<note type="footnote"> West Virginia
                            Alcohol Beverage Control Administration, Definition 2.1.</note> So in
                        West Virginia state law, the concept ›wine‹ includes products based on
                        pears, apples, and rice as long as they contain more than 7% and less than
                        24% ethanol, i. e. apparently all alcoholic beverages between these limits
                        that are not beer, since beer is discussed under a different heading. But
                        then again <quote>barley wine</quote> is identified as a kind of wine.
                        However, it shares all relevant properties with beer except its alcoholic
                        strength.</p>
                    <p>So the law is self-contradictory. If we wanted to model the taxonomy of
                        beverages in West Virginia state law, we would have to settle either for a
                        concept of wine that does include beverages made from barley and does not
                        require that its fermentation is based on sugar. Or we could disregard the
                        subsumption of barley ›wine‹ under the concept of wine, so that our model
                        remains incomplete.</p>
                    <p>Concepts in law are necessarily vague: courts must have the freedom to apply
                        the law to new beverages that were unknown when the legislation was written.
                        Stipulated meanings in a law can contradict our common-sense notions, so
                        that they cannot easily be mapped on existing ontologies that, like the wine
                        ontology, understand wine as potable liquid that is made from grape. The
                        occurrence of contradictions, vagueness, and tensions between concepts in
                        different domains can lead sceptics to the conclusion that, since concepts
                        are nothing but social constructions that do not follow the strict
                        requirements of the ontology engineer, the whole endeavour of modelling
                        knowledge in a machine-readable way is doomed. Conversely, realists would
                        probably point out that the legal meaning of ›wine‹ in West Virginia could
                        be reconstructed in principle, if we had functioning ontologies of artefacts
                        and social institutions. The resulting determination may be incredibly
                        complex, but feasible in principle.</p>
                    <p>Or we may wonder whether ›reification‹ can be a solution. RDF, an XML dialect
                        for describing web resources semantically, offers support for this
                        technique, so I will use its syntax to explain the notion.<note
                            type="footnote"> I discuss reification in RDF for the sake of
                            simplicity. Similar techniques are available for OWL. Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#stevens_reification_2010"
                                >Stevens / Lord 2010</ref>, passim.</note></p>
                    <p>RDF represents a reified statement as four statements with particular RDF
                        properties and objects: the statement (S, P, O), reified by resource R, is
                        represented by:</p>
                    <list type="unordered">
                        <item><code>R rdf:type rdf:Statement</code></item>
                        <item><code>R rdf:subject S</code></item>
                        <item><code>R rdf:predicate </code></item>
                        <item><code>R rdf:object O</code><note type="footnote">
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#apache_2011-2014">The Apache
                                    Foundation 2011–2014</ref>, section
                                <quote>Introduction</quote>.</note></item>
                    </list>
                    <p>The first triple (R rdf:type rdf:Statement) can be used to refer to the
                        statement that is composed of the tree terms S, P, and O. We could thus
                        refer to the concept <quote>Sake is legal wine in West Virginia</quote> by
                        simply naming the statement <quote>Sake_is_legal_wine_in_WV</quote> (or
                        SLWWV) and composing it out of the subject term <quote>Sake</quote>, the
                        relation <quote>is subclass of</quote>, and the object term
                            <quote>legal_wine_in_West_Virginia</quote>. Such a ›quadlet‹<note
                            type="footnote"> Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#stevens_reification_2010">Stevens / Lord 2010</ref>,
                            passim.</note> does allow us to refer to a statement as a whole. So we
                        could express the intentions of West Virginia legislators in formulating the
                        Legislative Rule by forming a second statement with <quote>West Virginia
                            legislators</quote> as subject term, <quote>stipulate</quote> as
                        relation term, and <quote>RLWWV</quote> as object term: West Virginia
                        legislators stipulate that Sake is legally wine in West Virginia.</p>
                    <p>But reification helps us only as long as the domain to be modelled is not
                        characterised by self-contradictory notions. If we wanted to reify the
                        statement <quote>barley wine is wine</quote>, we would run into problems.
                        Since barley wine is in fact stipulated to be beer and since the stipulation
                        for beer contradicts the stipulations for wine (beer is based on
                        fermentation of grain, wine is based on fermentation of sugar), any ontology
                        trying to capture the intentions of West Virginia legislators is bound to
                        fail, because these intentions contradict each other: a coherent model is
                        impossible. This is different from a situation in which we are merely unsure
                        about the factual truth or falsity of a statement: a reified statement can
                        be false as long as its falsehood is purely factual.<note type="footnote">
                            It is then covered by the ›open world assumption‹ (OWA), at least as
                            long as its truth or falsity is unknown. Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#drummond_open_2006">Drummond / Shearer 2006</ref>, slide 9:
                                <quote>The OWA assumes incomplete information by
                            default.</quote></note> But reification cannot salvage us from logical
                        or conceptual incoherence.</p>
                    <p>The way out of this quandary is to deny <quote>barley wine is wine</quote>
                        the status of a RDF statement. <quote>Barley wine is wine</quote> is just
                        the name of a statement containing a subject term, a relation term, and an
                        object term, but none of these terms is part of a RDF triple.<note
                            type="footnote"> The ›abstract syntax‹ for RDF (<ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#cyganiak_rdf_2014">Cyganiak et al. 2014</ref>, section 3.1)
                            prescribes that the subject term and the relation term of a RDF triple
                            contain IRIs and not just strings (›literals‹). For the notion of an IRI
                            cf. <ref type="bibliography" target="#duerst_rfc_2006">Duerst / Suignard
                                2006</ref>, section 1.1.</note> Hence their aggregation in a
                        statement does not constitute a RDF statement. This expresses the fact that
                        the status of this triple of terms as the description of a resource (i. e.
                        something ›out there‹) is uncertain. Since the reference of the statement is
                        unclear, the same must be presumed for its meaning (or lack thereof). The
                        meaning of the statement is opaque, even though we can specify the terms it
                        contains. But it is equally important to describe the content, whatever it
                        may be, as a propositional content that can be ascribed to the creators of
                        this statement, i. e. presumably legislators in the state of West
                        Virginia.</p>
                    <p>The main advantage of such an approach over proper reification is that it can
                        be used heuristically: we do not need a full blown ontology for capturing
                        the content of a given discourse in a form that is amenable to further
                        refinement and development. This heuristic approach is particularly useful
                        when we are interested in the connection between what has been said and who
                        said it, i. e. in all domains in which we capture opinions of people, i. e.
                        in all domains that proceed ›doxographically‹. And it can accommodate the
                        development of the intension of a concept over time and thus be helpful to
                        track the history of concepts, beliefs, and theories.</p>
                </div>
                <div type="chapter">
                    <head>4. A Use Case: Capturing a Philosophical Discourse Doxographically</head>
                    <p>If we want to condense the approach sketched in this paper into a handy
                        slogan, we could say that it focuses on what people say about the world
                        rather than on what there is in the world. It records opinions rather than
                        facts. In the history of philosophy, doxography, the recording of opinions,
                        is a venerable tradition going back to ancient times.<note type="footnote">
                            However, it should be noted that assessments of its relevance differ.
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#dillon_review_2006">Dillon
                                2006</ref> calls it <quote>a pretty low form of literature</quote>,
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#mansfeld_doxography_2013">Mansfeld
                                2013</ref> is less skeptical and compares ancient doxographical
                            writings to present-day secondary literature.</note> So the minimal
                        ontology for capturing opinions of others can be said to proceed
                        ›doxographically‹. It comprises abstract and spatiotemporal entities, namely
                        persons holding or texts articulating a certain belief and the propositional
                        content of the belief. Propositional attitudes can be understood as
                        properties of spatiotemporal entities, namely the property of asserting,
                        denying, or merely reflecting upon a given propositional content.</p>
                    <p> So the minimal ontology for capturing opinions of others can be said to
                        proceed ›doxographically‹. It comprises abstract and spatiotemporal
                        entities, namely persons holding or texts articulating a certain belief and
                        the propositional content of the belief. Propositional attitudes can be
                        understood as properties of spatiotemporal entities, namely the property of
                        asserting, denying, or merely reflecting upon a given propositional
                        content.</p>
                    <p>Such a minimal doxographical ontology can be used to capture the content of a
                        given discourse without making any assumptions about the conceptual
                        structure of the respective domain. In a proof of concept at <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/wiki/EMTO_Nanopub">EMTO
                            Nanopub</ref> I have assembled ›doxographical facts‹ about the debate on
                        how to define ›philosophy‹ in early modern Iberian philosophy, collating the
                        viewpoints of <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?search=GasparCardilloDeVillalpando&amp;title=Special:Search&amp;go=Go"
                            >Gaspar Cardillo de Villalpando</ref>, the <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=Complutenses&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Complutenses</ref>, the <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=Conimbricenses&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Conimbricenses</ref>, <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=DiegoMas&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Diego Mas</ref>, <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=VicenteMontanes&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Vicente Montanes</ref>, <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=AntonioRubio&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Antonio Rubio</ref>, <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/wiki/Jose_SaenzDeAguirre">José
                            Saenz de Aguirre</ref>, and <ref
                            target="http://emto-nanopub.referata.com/w/index.php?title=Special:Search&amp;profile=default&amp;search=franciscustoletus&amp;fulltext=Search"
                            >Franciscus Toletus</ref> as ›nanopublications‹.<note type="footnote">
                            On the concept of nanopublications and their uses in the humanities cf.
                                <ref type="bibliography" target="#heßbrueggen-walter_tatsachen_2013"
                                >Heßbrüggen-Walter 2013</ref>, passim.</note> Even without
                        additional conceptual analysis of these propositions, we can gain some
                        interesting insights from this purely doxographical ›record keeping‹.</p>
                    <p><figure>
                            <media type="svg" xml:id="ontology_2015_001"
                                url=".../medien/svg/ontology_2015_001.svg">
                                <desc><ref target="#abb1">fig. 1</ref>: Propositional contents in
                                    eight Iberian philosophers debating the proper definition of
                                    philosophy. For an interactive version, please open the <ref
                                        type="extern"
                                        target="http://www.zfdg.de/sites/default/files/medien/svg/ontology_2015_001.svg"
                                        >SVG-File</ref>. Javascript must be activated.</desc>
                            </media>
                        </figure></p>
                    <p><ref type="graphic" target="#ontology_2015_001">Figure 1</ref> shows a
                        network of the eight authors and the propositional content they assert, deny
                        or reflect upon in their texts about the proper definition of philosophy. It
                        has been produced in <hi rend="italic">gephi</hi>, a very comprehensive tool
                        for the production of network diagrams.<note type="footnote"> A presentation
                            of the guiding principles at work in <hi rend="italic">gephi </hi>can be
                            found in <ref type="bibliography" target="#bastian_gephi_2009"
                                >Bastian et al. 2009</ref>, passim.</note> The authors are displayed
                        as ›nodes‹ in this network diagram that only serve as starting points of
                        ›edges‹ (arrows). The edges themselves are coloured according to the
                        propositional attitude that exists between author and propositional content:
                        green arrows signify an assertion, red arrows a negation, grey arrows a
                        neutral stance (e. g. a quotation). Propositional contents are siginified by
                        those nodes in which edges end. Since the visualisation is quite complex,
                        zooming and panning is supported via the <ref
                            target="http://www.webcitation.org/query?url=http://www.cyberz.org/blog/2009/12/08/svgpan-a-javascript-svg-panzoomdrag-library/&amp;date=20"
                            >SVGpan</ref> library. This allows the viewer to explore the structure
                        of the presented network of authors and propositional contents
                        interactively. The points of arrows are linked to URLs of nanopublications
                        on EMTO-Nanopub.</p>
                    <p>Even a cursory inspection of this visualisation provides some interesting
                        insights into parameters that usually are not in the centrer of attention of
                        historians of philosophy. We can discern marked differences in the ratio of
                        grey arrows to coloured arrows in various authors. Antonio Rubio mostly
                        provides theses without taking an explicit stance: most of the arrows
                        starting from this node are grey. In contrast, Cardillo de Villalpando (at
                        the bottom of the figure) prefers a thetical style of writing and expresses
                        only things that are the case: all arrows starting from this node are green.
                        A second surprising result is that, even though many may view Spanish
                        scholasticism as a unified school of thought, many topics come up only in
                        one author. Only a minority of assertions or denials concern more than one
                        or two authors. Reflections like these may lead to a more precise
                        quantitative analysis of argumentative strategies, but would certainly not
                        have come into view by just reading the texts.</p>
                    <p>But beyond such ›stylometric‹ reflections, visualisations also help us to
                        understand the structure of a debate more precisely. Debates consist in
                        contents that are either asserted or denied. So we can omit all edges that
                        denote mere reflection on a given content and include only assertion and
                        negation as propositional attitudes (edges). And participants in a debate
                        are supposed to endorse at least one thesis that is endorsed or denied by
                        other participants as well.</p>
                    <p><figure>
                            <media type="svg" xml:id="ontology_2015_002"
                                url=".../medien/svg/ontology_2015_002.svg">
                                <desc><ref target="#abb2">fig. 2</ref>: Propositional contents that
                                    are asserted or denied in the debate on how to define
                                    philosophy. For an interactive version, please open the <ref
                                        type="extern"
                                        target="http://www.zfdg.de/sites/default/files/medien/svg/ontology_2015_002.svg"
                                        >SVG-File</ref>. Javascript must be activated.</desc>
                            </media>
                        </figure></p>
                    <p>To apply these two criteria simplifies the picture considerably. One author
                        drops out of the picture, because he does not fulfil the second criterion:
                        Rubio does not take a stance that is either asserted or denied by another
                        author in the debate. Apparently, there are two camps in the debate, one
                        that seems to focus on philosophy as knowledge of causes (in the upper
                        region of <ref type="graphic" target="#ontology_2015_002">figure 2</ref>)
                        and one that seems to be concerned with the nexus between philosophy and the
                        Divine (in the bottom region of the <ref type="graphic"
                            target="#ontology_2015_002">figure 2</ref>). The bridge between both
                        camps is built by Vicente Montañés who asserts contents that can be found in
                        both camps. This impression is reinforced when we simplify further and
                        include only those propositional contents that are asserted by at least two
                        thinkers (<ref type="graphic" target="#ontology_2015_003">figure
                        3</ref>):</p>
                    <p><figure>
                            <media type="svg" xml:id="ontology_2015_003"
                                url=".../medien/svg/ontology_2015_003.svg">
                                <desc><ref target="#abb3">fig. 3</ref>: Propositional contents that
                                    are asserted by at least two authors in the debate on how to
                                    define philosophy. For an interactive version, please open the
                                        <ref type="extern"
                                        target="http://www.zfdg.de/sites/default/files/medien/svg/ontology_2015_003.svg"
                                        >SVG-File</ref>. Javascript must be activated.</desc>
                            </media>
                        </figure></p>
                    <p>Two general points are worth emphasising: first, it should be noted that the
                        visualisations presented here are the result of algorithms for the
                        visualisation of networks implemented in <hi rend="italic">gephi</hi>. Some
                        minor redactions had to be added manually, but the overall representation of
                        the structure of the debate is not the result of conscious design decisions.
                        Since it is the machine that does the work of structuring the debate,
                        hermeneutic biases are minimised in this step. Second, this approach to
                        visualising excerpts of ›the history of philosophy‹ allows to trace each and
                        every ›visual assertion‹ to the relevant evidence, since every edge that
                        connects an author to a propositional content, i. e. every doxographical
                        statement, is linked to a nanopublication providing the bibliographical data
                        of the source text and the author making the doxographical statement.</p>
                    <p>›Doxography‹ is an essential, though mostly underrated, element in the
                        workflow of any historian of philosophy. Working with a text, we must first
                        produce summaries, excerpts, or other research notes that help us to fixate
                        its content, before we tackle the more complex task of reconstructing its
                        arguments, comparing them to other sources, and evaluating their validity
                        either in their historical context or in relation to contemporary problems.
                        To deal with this process using digital tools may in itself transform and
                        enhance existing practices in the history of philosophy. But, more
                        importantly, it also opens up new research questions and may change our
                        understanding of the discipline as a whole.</p>
                </div>
                <div type="chapter">
                    <head>5. Digital Doxography and Heuristic Ontologies: A Vision</head>
                    <p>In the use case presented here, the ›semantic‹ dimension of semantic web
                        technologies was conspicuously absent. But we can now articulate a broader
                        vision of how the heuristic use of ontologies could transform not merely the
                        record keeping of the digital doxographer, but transform our strategies of
                        interpreting philosophical sources.</p>
                    <p>One particularity of (at least some) philosophical theories consists in the
                        way that they try to develop conceptual hierarchies that quite easily could
                        be transformed into statements of an ontology. If we take for example the
                        following two propositional contents:</p>
                    <p><code>S:philosophy R:is O:habit</code></p>
                    <p><code>S:part of philosophy R:is O:species of philosophy</code></p>
                    <p>For an expert in the domain it is fairly obvious that the first triple
                        expresses a relation of conceptual subordination: It could thus be
                        transformed into a corresponding OWL statement:</p>
                    <p><code>&lt;owl:Class rdf:ID="philosophy"&gt;</code></p>
                    <p><code>&lt;rdfs:subClassOf rdf:resource="habit" /&gt;</code></p>
                    <p><code>&lt;/owl:Class&gt;</code></p>
                    <p>The second example expresses the identification of the extensions of two
                        concepts. Everything that is an example of the intension ›is part of
                        philosophy‹ is at the same time an example of the intension ›is a species of
                        philosophy‹. In other words, both concepts are, in the terminology of OWL,
                        equivalent classes:</p>
                    <p><code>&lt;owl:Class rdf:ID="part of philosophy"&gt;</code></p>
                    <p><code> &lt;rdfs:equivalentClassOf rdf:resource="species of philosophy"
                            /&gt;</code></p>
                    <p><code>&lt;/owl:Class&gt;</code></p>
                    <p>Of course, it is important to note that again we should not misconstrue such
                        statements as being concerned with philosophy as a thing in the world.<note
                            type="footnote"> This is a major difference to the goals of the Indiana
                            Philosophy Ontology Project that tries to capture a valid present day
                            understanding of philosophy as a scholarly discipline. Cf. <ref
                                type="bibliography" target="#buckner_encyclopedia_2011">Buckner et
                                al. 2011</ref>, passim.</note> These statements, too, must be
                        suitably qualified, namely as ›intentional objects‹ of philosophical thought
                        in a given period. And a second important caveat applies: by transforming
                        the isolated statements of a doxographical record into the reconstruction of
                        a conceptual scheme, we leave the domain of ›facts‹ and enter into the realm
                        of interpretation. The more complex a source text is, the more we may expect
                        deviations between different attempts of reconstruction. In this respect,
                        the use of code as a medium of interpretation does not change its
                        fundamental hermeneutic characteristics. But ontologies, understood as the
                        expression of a coherent vision of a given conceptual scheme, could
                        nevertheless develop into powerful tools for the historian of
                        philosophy.</p>
                    <p>This is particularly true for those domains in which mass digitisation
                        projects have made available large number of previously unknown or
                        inaccessible sources. Since we may expect some progress regarding optical
                        character recognition of historical prints, it is to be hoped that a large
                        number of these texts will at some time in the future be available as
                        machine-readable e-texts. And even though practitioners in the field assert
                        that natural language processing of Latin texts is difficult, because these
                        texts are written in Latin, some progress on this front will hopefully be
                        made too.<note type="footnote"> Cf. <ref type="bibliography"
                                target="#passarotti_leaving_2010">Passarotti 2010</ref>,
                            passim.</note> The upshot of this is that these developments may help us
                        in extracting doxographical triples from a large number of texts, both in
                        Latin and the vernaculars, in order to gain a deeper and more comprehensive
                        understanding of the historical record as it stands. The methodology
                        proposed here may then prove to be a fruitful strategy for turning this
                        content into semantically rich information.</p>
                </div>
                <div type="bibliography">
                    <head>Bibliographische Angaben</head>
                    <listBibl>
                        <bibl xml:id="apache_2011-2014">Apache Jena Documentation. Edited by The
                            Apache Foundation. 2011–2014. [<ref
                                target="https://jena.apache.org/documentation/notes/reification.html"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="bastian_gephi_2009">Mathieu Bastian / Sebastien
                            Heymann / Mathieu Jacomy: Gephi: An Open Source Software for Exploring
                            and Manipulating Networks. In: Proceedings of the Third International
                            ICWSMConference. 2009, S. 361–362. [<ref
                                target="http://www.aaai.org/ocs/index.php/ICWSM/09/paper/view/154"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="buckner_encyclopedia_2011">Cameron Buckner / Mathias
                            Niepert / Colin Allen: From encyclopedia to ontology: Toward dynamic
                            representation of the discipline of philosophy. In: Synthese 182 (2011),
                            H. 2, p. 205–233.[<ref
                                target="http://services.bibliothek.kit.edu/kvk/view-title/index.php?katalog=HEBIS&amp;url=http%3A%2F%2Fcbsopac.rz.uni-frankfurt.de%2FDB%3D2.1%2FCHARSET%3DUTF-8%2FIMPLAND%3DY%2FLNG%3DDU%2FSRT%3DYOP%2FTTL%3D1%2FCOOKIE%3DU203%2CK203%2CI251%2CB1999%2B%2B%2B%2B%2B%2B%2CSN%2CNDefault%2Blogin%2CD2.1%2CE599eccbe-1%2CA%2CH%2CR129.13.130.211%2CFY%2FSET%3D1%2FSHW%3FFRST%3D1&amp;showCoverImg=1"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="dillon_review_2006">John Dillon: Review of Aldo Brancacci
                            (ed.): Philosophy and Doxography in the Imperial Age. Firenze 2005. In:
                            Bryn Mawr Classical Review 12 (2006). [<ref
                                target="http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2006/2006-12-19.html"
                            >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="drummond_open_2006">Nick Drummond / Rob Shearer: The Open
                            World Assumption or Sometimes its nice to know what we don’t know.
                            Manchester 2006. [<ref
                                target="http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/~drummond/presentations/OWA.pdf"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="duerst_rfc_2006">M. Duerst / M. Suignard: RFC 3987:
                            Internationalized Resource Identifiers (IRIs). 2006. [<ref
                                target="http://www.ietf.org/rfc/rfc3987.txt">online</ref>] </bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="heßbrueggen-walter_tatsachen_2013">Stefan Heßbrüggen-Walter:
                            Tatsachen im semantischen Web: Nanopublikationen in den digitalen
                            Geisteswissenschaften? In: Historyblogosphere: Bloggen in den
                            Geschichtswissenschaften. Edited by Peter Haber / Eva Pfanzelter.
                            München 2013, p. 149–160. <ptr type="gbv" cRef="718336836"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="jansen_artefakte_2013">Ludger Jansen: Warum sich Artefakte
                            ihrer Marginalisierung widersetzen. In: Deutsche Zeitschrift für
                            Philosophie 61 (2013), H. 2, p. 267–282. <ptr type="opac"
                                cRef="129464090"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="janssen_frege_2001">Theo M.V. Janssen: Frege, Contextuality
                            and Compositionality. In: Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10
                            (2001), H. 1, p. 115–136. <ptr type="gbv" cRef="131091077"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="kemmann_grasping_2014">Max Kemmann: Grasping Technology. Juni
                            2014. [<ref
                                target="http://www.maxkemman.nl/2014/06/grasping-technology/"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="kohle_bildwissenschaft_2013">Hubertus Kohle: Digitale
                            Bildwissenschaft. Glückstadt 2013. <ptr type="opac" cRef="745036228"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="lemanski_urspruenge_2013">Jens Lemanski: Die
                            neuaristotelischen Ursprünge des Kontextprinzips und die Fortführung in
                            der fregeschen Begriffsschrift. In: Zeitschrift für philosophische
                            Forschung 67 (2013), H. 4, p. 566–586. <ptr type="opac" cRef="129465615"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="heath_linked_">Linked Open Data – Frequently Asked Questions.
                            Edited by Tom Heath. [<ref target="http://linkeddata.org/faq"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="mansfeld_doxography_2013">Jaap Mansfeld: Doxography of Ancient
                            Philosophy. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013
                            Edition). Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2013. [<ref
                                target="http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/doxography-ancient/"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>
                        <bibl xml:id="noy_ontology_2001">N. F. Noy / D. L. McGuiness: Ontology
                            Development 101: A Guide to Creating Your First Ontology. 2001. [<ref
                                target="http://www.ksl.stanford.edu/KSL_Abstracts/KSL-01-05.html"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="dean_ontology_2004">OWL Web Ontology Language Reference.
                            Edited by Mike Dean / Guus Schreiber. 2004 [<ref
                                target="http://www.w3.org/TR/owl-ref/">online</ref>].</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="passarotti_leaving_2010">Marco Carlo Passarotti: Leaving
                            Behind the Less-Resourced Status. The Case of Latin through the
                            Experience of the Index Thomisticus Treebank. In: 7th SaLTMiL Workshop
                            on Creation and Use of Basic Lexical Resources for Less-Resourced
                            Languages, LREC 2010. La Valletta 2010. 2010, p. 27–32. [<ref
                                target="http://ixa2.si.ehu.es/~jipsagak/SALTMIL2010_Proceedings.pdf"
                                >online</ref>] </bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="cyganiak_rdf_2014">RDF 1.1 Concepts and Abstract Syntax.
                            Edited by Richard Cyganiak / David Wood / Markus Lanthaler. 2014. [<ref
                                target="http://www.w3.org/TR/rdf11-concepts/">online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="shirky_ontology_">Clay Shirky: Ontology is Overrated:
                            Categories, Links, and Tags. [<ref
                                target="http://www.shirky.com/writings/ontology_overrated.html"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="smith_ontology_2014">Barry Smith: Beyond Concepts: Ontology as
                            Reality Representation. In: Proceedings of FOIS 2004. Edited by Achille
                            Varzi / Laure Vieu. Amsterdam, Berlin, Oxford, Tokyo, Washington DC
                            2014, p. 73–84. <ptr type="opac" cRef="492551804"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="stainton_context_2006">R. J. Stainton: Context Principle. In:
                            Encyclopedia of Language &amp; Linguistics, vol. 3, Boston 2006, p.
                            108–115. <ptr type="gbv" cRef="473039672"/></bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="stevens_reification_2010">Robert Stevens / Phillip Lord:
                            Reification of properties in an ontology. 2010. [<ref
                                target="http://ontogenesis.knowledgeblog.org/993"
                            >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="title175_">Title 175, Legislative Rule Series 2 Private Club
                            Licensing. Edited by West Virginia Alcohol Beverage Commissioner. [<ref
                                target="http://www.abca.wv.gov/CodeRules/Documents/175-02.pdf"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>

                        <bibl xml:id="szabo_compositionality_2013">Zoltán Gendler Szabó:
                            »Compositionality«. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall
                            2013 Edition). Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2013. [<ref
                                target="http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/compositionality/"
                                >online</ref>]</bibl>
                    </listBibl>
                </div>
                <div type="abbildungsnachweis">
                    <head>Abbildungslegenden und -nachweise</head>
                    <desc type="graphic" xml:id="abb1">Propositional contents in eight
                        Iberian philosophers debating the proper definition of philosophy (The
                        rendering of SVG files may vary from browser to browser. Zooming and panning
                        requires the activation of Javascript) (graphic: author).<ref type="graphic"
                            target="#ontology_2015_001"/></desc>
                    <desc type="graphic" xml:id="abb2">Propositional contents that are
                        asserted or denied in the debate on how to define philosophy (graphic:
                            author).<ref type="graphic" target="#ontology_2015_002"/></desc>
                    <desc type="graphic" xml:id="abb3">Propositional contents that are
                        asserted by at least two authors in the debate on how to define philosophy
                        (graphic: author).<ref type="graphic" target="#ontology_2015_003"/></desc>
                </div>
            </div>
        </body>
    </text>
</TEI>